Parrhesia

Share this post

Don't Fight the Hypothetical

parrhesia.substack.com

Don't Fight the Hypothetical

If you want to have a productive philosophical conversation, you need to be willing to entertain hypothetical scenarios.

Ives Parr
Apr 8, 2022
6
4
Share this post

Don't Fight the Hypothetical

parrhesia.substack.com

My favorite philosopher Michael Huemer has written a philosophy textbook Knowledge, Reality, and Value, in which he takes a section to describe how to be a good interlocutor when talking about philosophy. His first principle is that you should be cooperative. One important feature of being cooperative is that you should accept hypothetical situations without raising a huge fuss over unimportant details.

If someone gives a hypothetical example, do not raise objections to the example that will only make your interlocutor waste time thinking of other examples, or thinking of a series of increasingly elaborate modifications to the example. Do not start a debate about how realistic the example is or “what would really happen” in a situation of that kind; just accept the example as the other person intended it.

The person providing the hypothetical example is trying to illustrate something. Tangential discussions about plausibility and workarounds aren’t addressing the central issue. If you respond to the trolley problem by suggesting that you would try to move the switch halfway in-between left and right to run the trolley off the track to save all six people, you are missing the point. All that this does is frustrate your interlocutor and make them devise a more complicated scenario to get you to address the central issue.

Scott Alexander recalls a similar example in his article The Least Convenient Possible World. When faced with the organ harvesting thought experiment in which a doctor can harvest the organs from an innocent traveler to save several people’s lives, one of Scott’s friend’s responded by saying:

It wouldn't be moral. After all, people often reject organs from random donors. The traveller would probably be a genetic mismatch for your patients, and the transplantees would have to spend the rest of their lives on immunosuppressants, only to die within a few years when the drugs failed.

While this is an interesting consideration, we can see how it doesn’t address the central issue. The point isn’t to note something about genetic mismatch, it is to see what someone thinks is the right choice in a difficult ethical dilemma. I think that hypotheticals are often avoided when they create a tension between someone’s intuitive sense of the good and someone’s ethical code. For example, it’s likely the friend was a utilitarian who thought the organ harvesting would be utility-maximizing, and yet they felt it was intuitively wrong to non-consensually take someone’s organs.

This happens a lot when I have ethical discussions. Many people adhere to one-sentence ethical theories such as radical libertarianism or utilitarianism. I think that we have ethical intuitions that give us access to moral knowledge, and that these intuitions don’t support single-sentence theories of ethics. If I see someone express the belief that ethics can be reduced to a single sentence, I attempt to find a counter-example that creates tension between their intuitions and their theory. When this happens, people fight the hypothetical.

Imagine that someone said it was always wrong to lie, and I asked them if they would lie to protect someone from an axe murderer. I think intuitively they would believe it was okay to lie in that situation. For that reason, they may say that they don’t need to respond to unlikely scenarios. Hardly anyone is killed via axe murderer and even if that was going to happen, it’s unlikely you would have to lie to protect them. While that is true, it is still worth answering the question. Just because something is unlikely to occur does not mean that it can be dismissed outright.

If we were discussing geopolitics, and I asked someone to consider what would happen if China invaded the Bahamas, I doubt that they would object on grounds that it was a low-probability event. We could have a meaningful conversation about this hypothetical world. Maybe the USA would react by sanctioning China. Maybe Cuba would react by preparing to defend itself against a Chinese invasion. Even if it is a waste of time, it might be worthwhile to entertain the idea to be a cooperative participant in a conversation.

Another objection to the axe murderer situation is that I am trying to normalize lying. I could agree that it is generally not ethical to lie, but is ethical in extreme circumstances. Finding one scenario doesn’t mean I want it to be regarded as generally okay. Besides, I have no problem with the idea that it’s most often bad to lie. I have an issue when people make extreme and absolute moral statements. The reason that I devise hypotheticals is to test someone’s actual commitment to the extreme position. Even if you think that I am trying to normalize lying, you can still answer the hypothetical while also expressing that you don’t think it generalizes to all situations.

I’m skeptical that people would have such a reaction to unusual scenarios if it is not in conflict with their beliefs. For example, I could ask if I should lie to a cashier to get away with stealing alcohol to give to some seven-year-olds outside the local gas station. I think most would easily respond with no. It goes against many ethical intuitions and conflicts with almost everyone’s ethical principles. I am doubtful that people would say the idea of a 7-year-old being unaccompanied and wanting alcohol is highly improbable and so they don't have to entertain this. Even if it’s a waste of time to entertain it, at least respond yes or no before the spiel about how it’s a dumb question.

Analogously, imagine that someone said the function g(x) is larger than the function f(x) everywhere. If I pointed out that it wasn’t true for the number fifty billion, then the statement is falsified. You shouldn’t say that fifty billion is a particularly large number or that it works for most numbers. If that’s the case, then just say that at the outset. What an extreme counter-example suggests is that your theory is false and that the method of reasoning used to derive it is suspect. Even if it is merely an extreme example of a single principle, it should cast doubt on your other moral principles. You’re doing something incorrect to reach your conclusions.

If I was teaching students about probability, I could ask what the probability of me getting two heads after flipping a coin twice is. A clever student could say "Coins are not perfectly balanced and you cannot flip the coin in a perfectly random way and so we can't know what the probability is." If I said "just let the probability be 50-50" the student could respond "Why should I trust you? That sounds extremely suspect to think that a perfect coin could exist." And if I went "Okay, imagine a Bernoulli random variable with p=.50" the student could object "there exists no such random variable in reality." This would all be a very tedious process. Ultimately, we know that probabilistic reasoning is legitimate even if it is not perfectly representative of real-world events. So, what function does fighting the hypothetical serve?

If you have a law of morality, then the law needs to apply everywhere. If a scenario could conceivably occur and your moral theory says in all circumstances do X, then in this scenario you should do X. My position is that you can always find a scenario where X is counter-intuitive. You can either bite the bullet or modify your theory, but I think objecting to hypotheticals generally is not a fair approach. It sounds reasonable to say you only respond to real scenarios, but I can't find a legitimate reason as to why we cannot entertain low-probability or impossible hypotheticals. These are often insightful in a way similar to talking about coinflips, even if you can’t have a perfect coinflip. When you find a counter-example to an absolute ethical theory, it is suggestive that your reasoning process for reaching that ethical theory is wrong.

4
Share this post

Don't Fight the Hypothetical

parrhesia.substack.com
4 Comments
Adrian Salustri
Writes Big Brain Takes
Apr 28, 2022Liked by Ives Parr

I'm not sure I agree with this. Complaining about pedantic objections to hypothetical is a sort of "double standard"

Remember, a hypothetical takes an abstract idea and lets us reason "by proxy" in a more familiar context. In this case, it's hard to talk about moral decisions in the abstract, so we concoct situations that best illustrate our point.

So when someone responds, even if you think it's stupid and unproductive, you need to remember that their general response is also "coded" in the same way your general argument is (through the hypothetical). They are also trying to illustrate something.

For example,

- the organ transplant guy was arguing how the uncertainty is so large that getting involved would be unjustifiable. Ethical dilemmas usually trivialize uncertainty, so it's a good objection.

-The guy who suggests derailing the trolley by pulling switch halfway is arguing that the moral thing is to spend your time finding a third option, even if it ends up being futile. If "the point" is to "see what someone thinks is the right choice in a difficult ethical dilemma", what more do you want?

- The kid is really asking: "why do the exact probabilities not matter?" There's a deep, interesting misunderstanding about probability theory under the hood here, but you'll only notice when you realize that the kid (the interlocutor) is thinking about this for the first time. They cant switch between abstract and concrete as quickly, so they won't articulate it as such.

I know its ironic that I'm pedantically picking apart your hypotheticals, but Im just trying to show how there is a lot of info in "stupid" answers. We should put in the work to generalize their responses in the same way we expect them to generalize our hypothetical.

I think Huemer just meant "be humble and listen before you object the premise", which goes both ways I guess. -A

Expand full comment
Reply
Resident Contrarian
Writes Resident Contrarian
Apr 11, 2022Liked by Ives Parr

I think I agree abstractly, but disagree on practical grounds in certain situations. Consider someone who presents me with the violinist/abortion philosophy thing. In almost any case I run into that, someone is not just blandly trying to get me thinking - they are trying to win an argument about abortion. The guy who wrote the thought problem might not be that way, but let's say almost everyone else is using that as a tool to promote a view or "win" during a disagreement.

I contrast that against something like the trolley problem, that really IS generally about just making people think, discussion, and learning.

If it's the latter, I agree with you on most points as far as I've thought it through. But in the case of the former, scrutiny of the premise starts to make a lot more sense and be a lot more necessary, because it's now part of a greater argument that overflows into real-world policy and decisions. So I'll start to ask why we chose an adult and not a baby (considering that in the real world we weight the protection of children heavier than we do for adults in almost every case) or why the person who needs to be strapped to the violinist is presented as completely unassociated from them, etc.

We might still come to the same conclusions in the long run, but I think there is a "I can't let you score points for free" incentive in some cases here.

Expand full comment
Reply
2 replies by Ives Parr and others
2 more comments…
TopNewCommunity

No posts

Ready for more?

© 2023 Ives Parr
Privacy ∙ Terms ∙ Collection notice
Start WritingGet the app
Substack is the home for great writing